alexandræ | ||||||||||||
|
constructing birestrictions with specific jectivitiesnovember 16th, 2024Let \(f:I\to J,\) as well as \(I_0\subset I\) and \(J_0\supset f(I_0).\) The map birestriction of \(f\) on \(I_0\to J_0\) is the map \(f\big|_{I_0}^{J_0}\) of type \(I_0\to J_0\) such that, for all \(x\in I_0,\) we have \(f\big|_{I_0}^{J_0}(x)=f(x).\) The possible jectivities of a map \(f:I\to J\) are the following :
Proof \(f\big|_\varnothing^\varnothing\) is of type \(\varnothing\to\varnothing.\) Thus, it's injective if and only if : $$\forall x\in\varnothing.\forall y\in\varnothing.(f(x)=f(y)\implies x=y)$$ This is true by principle of explosion. Likewise, it's surjective if and only if : $$\forall y\in\varnothing.\exists x\in\varnothing.f(x)=y$$ This is also true by principle of explosion. It is therefore both injective and surjective, thus proving its bijectivity. \(\blacksquare\)Theorem 1.2 Given any \(f:I\to J,\) the map \(f\big|_\varnothing^{\{*\}}\) is injective and non-surjective. Proof \(f\big|_\varnothing^{\{*\}}\) is of type \(\{*\}\to\varnothing.\) Thus, it's injective if and only if : $$\forall x\in\varnothing.\forall y\in\varnothing.(f(x)=f(y)\implies x=y)$$ This is true by principle of explosion. Likewise, it's surjective if and only if : $$\forall y\in\{*\}.\exists x\in\varnothing.f(x)=y$$ However, \(\exists x\in\varnothing.f(x)=*\) is always false, which means it's always always non-surjective. \(\blacksquare\) Lemma 1.3 Given any non-injective \(f:I\to J,\) there exists \(*\in J\) such that \(f^{-1}(\{*\})\) has at least two distinct elements. Proof By algebraic manipulation, \begin{equation*} \begin{split} &\neg\forall x\in I.\forall y\in I.(f(x)=f(y)\implies x=y)\\ \dashv\vdash &\exists x\in I.\neg\forall y\in I.(f(x)=f(y)\implies x=y)\text{ by conversion of quantifiers}\\ \dashv\vdash &\exists x\in I.\exists y\in I.\neg(f(x)=f(y)\implies x=y)\text{ by }\!\!\left\{\!\!\begin{array}{ll}\text{conversion of quantifiers}\\\text{covariance of existential sentences' last components}\end{array}\right.\\ \dashv\vdash &\exists x\in I.\exists y\in I.\neg(\neg f(x)=f(y)\vee x=y)\text{ by }\!\!\left\{\!\!\begin{array}{ll}\text{material implication}\\\text{contravariance of negated components}\\\text{covariance of existential sentences' last components}\end{array}\right.\\ \dashv\vdash &\exists x\in I.\exists y\in I.(\neg\neg f(x)=f(y)\land\neg x=y)\text{ by }\!\!\left\{\!\!\begin{array}{ll}\text{De Morgan laws}\\\text{covariance of existential sentences' last components}\\\text{covariance of conjunctions' components}\end{array}\right.\\ \dashv\vdash &\exists x\in I.\exists y\in I.(f(x)=f(y)\land\neg x=y)\text{ by }\!\!\left\{\!\!\begin{array}{ll}\text{double negation elimination}\\\text{covariance of existential sentences' last components}\\\text{covariance of conjunctions' components}\end{array}\right.\\ \dashv\vdash &\exists x\in I.\exists y\in I.(\neg x=y\land f(x)=f(y))\text{ by }\!\!\left\{\!\!\begin{array}{ll}\text{commutativity of conjunction}\\\text{covariance of existential sentences' last components}\end{array}\right. \end{split} \end{equation*} Let \(x,y\in I\) such that \(\neg x=y\) and \(f(x)=f(y).\) If we define \(*:=f(x)=f(y)\in J,\) this ensures \(f^{-1}(\{*\})\) has at least two distinct elements, \(x\) and \(y.\) Therefore, \(|f^{-1}(\{*\})|\ge2.\) \(\blacksquare\)Theorem 1.4 Given any non-injective \(f:I\to J,\) and any \(*\in J\) with distinct preimages \(x,y\in f^{-1}(\{*\}),\) we have that \(f\big|_{\{x,y\}}^{\{*\}}\) is surjective and non-injective. Proof \(f\big|_{\{x,y\}}^{\{*\}}\) is non-injective, as \(f(x)=*=f(y)\) while \(x\ne y.\) However, it is surjective, because its image \(f\big|_{\{x,y\}}^{\{*\}}(\{x,y\})=\{f(x),f(y)\}=\{*\}\) is its codomain. \(\blacksquare\)Theorem 1.5 Given any non-injective \(f:I\to J,\) and any \(*\in J\) with distinct preimages \(x,y\in f^{-1}(\{*\}),\) we have that \(f\big|_{\{x,y\}}^{\{*,\{*\}\}}\) is neither surjective nor injective. Proof \(f\big|_{\{x,y\}}^{\{*\}}\) is non-injective, as \(f(x)=*=f(y)\) while \(x\ne y.\) It isn't surjective either, because \(f\big|_{\{x,y\}}^{\{*,\{*\}\}}(\{x,y\})=\{f(x),f(y)\}=\{*\}\) is a proper subset of its codomain \(\{*,\{*\}\},\) as \({*}\ne\{*\}\) due to an infamous corollary of the axiom of regularity.Example. By applying the four previous theorems, we can take two sets \(I,J\subset\mathbb R\) such that the \(f:I\to J\) defined as \(x\mapsto x^2\) is such that :
Theorem 1.6 Given \(f:I\to J,\) and any birestriction \(f\big|_{I_0}^{J_0},\) we have the following :
ProofOverall, these results provide us with an universal (trivial) injective (non-surjective) map birestriction, and (trivial) bijective map birestriction. On the other hand, getting a non-injective map birestriction requires finding elements of the original map's codomain that have multiple preimages ; therefore, there is no universal non-injective map birestriction. However... Theorem 1.7 Given any \(f:I\to J,\) the map birestriction \(f\big|_I^{f(I)}\) is surjective. Proof By definition, \(f(I)\) is the set of all images of elements of \(I\) by \(f,\) which therefore guarantees surjectivity. \(\blacksquare\)Theorem 1.8 If \(f\) is non-injective, then \(f\big|_I^{f(I)}\) is surjective non-injective. Proof By non-injectivity of \(f,\) there exist \(x,y\in I\) such that \(x\ne y\) and \(f(x)=f(y).\) Then, \(f\big|_I^{f(I)}(x)=f\big|_I^{f(I)}(y),\) despite \(x\ne y,\) which proves its non-injectivity. \(\blacksquare\)Corollary 1.9 If \(f\) is non-injective, then \(f\big|_I^{f(I)\cup\{f(I)\}}\) is neither surjective nor injective. Proof \(f\big|_I^{f(I)}\) is already non-injective surjective thanks to theorem 1.8, but \(f(I)\not\in f(I)\) by a corollary of the axiom of regularity, so \(f\big|_I^{f(I)\cup\{f(I)\}}\) is neither injective nor surjective. \(\blacksquare\)
| |||||||||||